ReviewEssays.com - Term Papers, Book Reports, Research Papers and College Essays
Search

Russell's Theory of Descriptions and Its Critics

Essay by   •  November 27, 2010  •  Research Paper  •  1,683 Words (7 Pages)  •  2,032 Views

Essay Preview: Russell's Theory of Descriptions and Its Critics

Report this essay
Page 1 of 7

The introduction to the "theory of descriptions" was written by Bertrand Russell in an article titled "On Denoting" in 1905 and is one of the most studied chapters in analytic philosophy. It is said, "...the choice of whether to accept or reject Russell's theory has had profound consequences for our philosophy of language, epistemology, and metaphysics."

One of Russell's motivations for developing the "theory of descriptions" was his abandonment of his "theory of denoting concepts," which is simply put as "the way of accommodating indirect aboutness." The "theory of denoting concepts" works such that where you are given a definite or indefinite description inside of a sentence, the sentence is made to state not the objects that it corresponds to, but instead, states a concept which contains those objects. Russell devoted a large amount of time trying to work out the details of this theory. The point where Russell changed direction from his "theory of denoting concepts" to his "theory of descriptions," was when he started to accept the views of the Meinongian argument. It was not until later when Russell realized in the years between the "theory of denoting concepts" and his discovery of "the theory of descriptions" that he did not fully commit to the Meinongian argument and that there were reasons he should not believe in it at all. We see this to be true in Russell's work, My Philosophical Development, when he admits that before his discovery of the theory of descriptions, Meinong had him convinced that if a person were to say that something such as unicorn did not exist that it ultimately had to exist in some realm or else your statement would be absolutely meaningless.

Hylton's text explains that despite the accusations delivered to Russell about adopting the "theory of descriptions" merely to avoid the Meinongian argument, there are four other reasons that may better serve to explain Russell's intentions.

Russell explained, "the theory of descriptions gives us an analysis of definite descriptionsÐ'...which is well integrated with the needs of logic." This meant that the ability to reason from factual knowledge, which involves definite descriptions, is a matter of "ordinary knowledge." Russell sought to do so in hopes of keeping the lines of logic as uncomplicated as possible.

Second, Russell realized that his former theory, the "theory of concepts" was open to many internal difficulties such as a proposition that is about any given denoting concept cannot contain that denoting concept. This means that it would be about its denotation. Russell says that for this to happen, a proposition that is about a denoting concept can only be indirectly about it. This in itself causes an "infinite hierarchy" that Hylton explains is too lengthy to be covered.

Third, Hylton says that Russell's own "theory of denoting concepts" was not up to Russell's standards. The theory explains generalities such as the proposition that "all prime numbers are odd." Russell says that this proposition contains the denoting concept all prime numbers, which is the mechanism for explaining that if a number is odd it is a prime number. Hylton says that this concept works for simple ideas such as this, but when we come to more complex ideas, such as a sentence with two or more variables, we cannot go forward with the connection unless certain assumptions are to be made.

Fourth, Hylton says that Russell's theory contradicted direct realism, which is what Russell's entire view on Philosophy was based on. The "theory of denoting concepts" gave no explanation to the exceptions that were made to direct realism.

The theory is setup to describe singular descriptions such as phrases that begin with the word "the", where a specific subject is the object. An example of this would be, "the man is white." This is a definite description and Russell shortens the term to merely Ð''descriptions'. We would deduce from this sentence that there is exactly one man and that he is white. We know that there is a man who is white, but we do not have knowledge of this man by acquaintance. We know there is a man, but we do not know who he is. To say there is exactly one man who is white would have to be false though because we can easily say that there could possibly be more then one man in the entire universe who is white. When we use this type of sentence, we often are referring to subjects within a restricted setting as to denote that there may be exactly one person who has the property of something.

Russell's classic example statement to help illustrate his theory is "The present king of France is bald." Since we very well know that there is no King of France, it must be false. However, if we were to take the sentence's negation to be, "The present King of France is not bald," we still find that the sentence seems to be false. The question now is whether pursuing this dilemma further is even worth the trouble. Russell would say yes and at the same time, many believed it not to be.

According to Russell's "theory of descriptions", the statement "the present King of France is bald" actually presupposes three unique assertions:

1. there is an x such that x is the King of France

2. there is no y, y is not equal to x, such that y is the King of France

3. x is bald

From this, we would be able to clearly see that the first assertion is false and since our statement is a combination of all three assertions, our statement must be false.

In Russell's book, The Problem Of Philosophy, Russell attributes our ideas of description to our acquaintance of an object. "The fundamental principle in the analysis of propositions containing descriptions is this: Every proposition which we can understand must be composed wholly of constituents with which we are acquainted."

Russell's theory was not unsusceptible to criticism though, and one of the major advocates again his theory came from Peter F. Strawson. In Strawson's first objection

...

...

Download as:   txt (9.7 Kb)   pdf (142.6 Kb)   docx (12.6 Kb)  
Continue for 6 more pages »
Only available on ReviewEssays.com
Citation Generator

(2010, 11). Russell's Theory of Descriptions and Its Critics. ReviewEssays.com. Retrieved 11, 2010, from https://www.reviewessays.com/essay/Russell's-Theory-of-Descriptions-and-Its-Critics/15837.html

"Russell's Theory of Descriptions and Its Critics" ReviewEssays.com. 11 2010. 2010. 11 2010 <https://www.reviewessays.com/essay/Russell's-Theory-of-Descriptions-and-Its-Critics/15837.html>.

"Russell's Theory of Descriptions and Its Critics." ReviewEssays.com. ReviewEssays.com, 11 2010. Web. 11 2010. <https://www.reviewessays.com/essay/Russell's-Theory-of-Descriptions-and-Its-Critics/15837.html>.

"Russell's Theory of Descriptions and Its Critics." ReviewEssays.com. 11, 2010. Accessed 11, 2010. https://www.reviewessays.com/essay/Russell's-Theory-of-Descriptions-and-Its-Critics/15837.html.