ReviewEssays.com - Term Papers, Book Reports, Research Papers and College Essays
Search

Arguments Against Skepticism

Essay by   •  December 17, 2010  •  Research Paper  •  4,094 Words (17 Pages)  •  2,204 Views

Essay Preview: Arguments Against Skepticism

Report this essay
Page 1 of 17

If I tried to simply tell a skeptic, "That rock will fall from the cliff because of gravity," he won't believe me because he will simply say, "Not necessarily." In fact, this can be the skeptic's answer to just about any attempt to refute his position.

It has long been pointed out by opponents of skepticism that such an attitude cannot be taken to its extreme conclusion in the real world in which we operate- even skeptics must live their lives according to rules they must rely upon not to fail. Skepticism (and all philosophy) cannot avoid the cumbersome nature of human language and the simple fact that the only tool humans have to investigate the nature of existence is the brain, which spawns coherent thoughts in a lingual form. In day to day life, realistically, the observations and calculations of the brain must be relied upon to reach trustworthy conclusions. The ardent skeptic will certainly not step off of a cliff unless he has a death wish. Obviously anyone who disregarded the law of gravity would be called insane. Therefore, it seems reasonable to accept the reliability of the laws of science. When arguing for his skeptical position, the skeptic would be forced to call into question the reliability of these laws in his refutation of absolute truth, attainable knowledge, etc. This is an apparently irrational behavior by the skeptic- to live by laws that he will later claim unknowable or altogether false. If one chooses to ignore this obvious fact, there is little that can be done to argue, for argument assumes that rational thought processes are at work. As Hank Hanegraaff has said, "Even those who deny reality look both ways before they cross the street."

One popular example skeptics use to disprove attainable knowledge is the Brain in the Vat argument. "The Brain in the Vat scenario is a thought experiment designed to show the plausibility of radical skepticism. If we were merely Brains in Vats, hooked to computers which send the same sorts of electrical impulses that a normal body would have, we would have experiences indistinguishable from "real life" experiences with no hope of discovering our predicament. Thus, it is possible, according to those who find this example compelling, that radical skepticism, the thesis that we have no certain knowledge, is true. The Brain in a Vat scenario was responded to by Hilary Putnam to promote his version of the argument for the claim that radical skepticism has to be false. He uses a version of the private language argument to argue that a brain in a vat would have no true beliefs. A brain in a vat which was causally hooked up to receive the same inputs it would have received if it had been in a body would, ex hypothesi the radical skeptic's theory, believe the same things we believe. But it would have no public referent for its words and sentences, and hence couldn't have any human language, since on Putnam's view, all languages require public referents. Thus, he argues that the skeptic who thinks all of our belief are (or could be) false has to suppose that we are like brains in vats. But since brains in vats could not have a language, and we do..."

Rudolf Carnap and Skepticism

"Can we know that things exist independent of our linguistic frameworks? This, of course, is the traditional problem of skepticism. Carnap has a relatively straightforward answer to the skeptic: ``To be real in the scientific sense means to be an element of the system; hence this concept cannot be meaningfully applied to the system itself.'' In other words, it is meaningless to make claims about objects independent of linguistic frameworks. Carnap would see this as analogous to asking questions about the absolute ontological status of `first base' independently of the game of baseball.

Accusing a question of being ``meaningless'' is not Carnap's last word on external questions. Carnap allows that some kinds of pragmatic criteria can be used in choosing a linguistic framework. In fact, he even gestures toward the attractive view that the acceptance of our ordinary language of things is part of a long historical process. However, insofar as the skeptic poses the external question from the comfort of her armchair, Carnap will reply that ``Unless and until they supply a clear cognitive interpretation, we are justified in our suspicion that their question is a pseudo-question, that is, one disguised in the form of a theoretical question while in fact it is non-theoretical Ð'...'"****

"Calling philosophical propositions meaningless is usually very antagonistic; it amounts to using fighting words. Some of the less thoughtful critics of Carnap see him as (solely) making this kind of pejorative value judgment. Those who use ``positivist'' as a kind of academic curse word regard Carnap as merely arguing that philosophers should find something more useful (and more scientific!) to do than chasing their tails worrying about skepticism. This image of an antagonistic stance is bolstered by Carnap's intimate involvement with the Vienna Circle who is known to have gone through the Tractatus line-by-line declaring each proposition true, false, or meaningless. While there are certainly overtones of this pejorative attitude, a moment's reflection on the text will show how this is a completely wrongheaded interpretation of the claim that skepticism is a meaningless doctrine.

For Carnap, a terms gets its meaning only in virtue of its role within a linguistic framework. ``If someone wishes to speak in his language about a new kind of entities [sic], he has to introduce a system of new ways of speaking, subject to new rules; we shall call this procedure the construction of a linguistic framework for the new entities in question.'' Since the skeptical problem as it is traditionally formulated is asked from outside a linguistic framework, it is quite literally meaningless. That which gives a linguistic expression meaning is absent. Thus far from a mere insult, calling an expression meaningless amounts to declaring it literally void of semantic content.

Having dealt with a superficial worry, let us turn to a more substantial one. Carnap argues that questions about the reality of the external world are meaningless. Yet can we not imagine a state of affairs in which we are systematically deceived about the external world? We can imagine (even if we think that it is false) that we are brains in vats and that the real world does not correspond to our experiences. If we can imagine this state of affairs, then how can it be meaningless? This is a much more interesting worry and in trying to understand Carnap's response to it, I think that his position comes into sharper focus." ****

"In

...

...

Download as:   txt (24.1 Kb)   pdf (239.1 Kb)   docx (18.3 Kb)  
Continue for 16 more pages »
Only available on ReviewEssays.com